Check out my first novel, midnight's simulacra!

Programming Language Theory: Difference between revisions

From dankwiki
Line 23: Line 23:


===Untyped λ-calculus===
===Untyped λ-calculus===
BNF grammar:
<pre>λ-term ::= λ-app | λ-abst | var
λ-app ::= λ-term λ-term
λ-abst ::= 'λ'var'.' λ-term</pre>
Two operators (function ''definition'' and ''application'') upon one operand type (λ-expression).
Two operators (function ''definition'' and ''application'') upon one operand type (λ-expression).
* Function definition: <tt>(λ''boundparam''. body)</tt>
* Function definition: <tt>(λ''boundparam''. body)</tt>
* Function application: <tt>function(''actualparam'')</tt>
* Function application: <tt>function(''actualparam'')</tt>
The body is made up of ''free'' and ''bound'' variables. Those not present in the λ's list of bound variables are free. A λ-expression with no free variables is ''closed'' (closed expressions are equivalent in power to [[Programming_Language_Theory#Combinatory_Logic|combinatory logic]]). Changing the names of bound variables within a λ-expression preserves ''ɑ-equivalence''.
The body is made up of ''free'' and ''bound'' variables. Those not present in the λ's list of bound variables are free. A λ-expression with no free variables is ''closed'' (closed expressions are equivalent in power to [[Programming_Language_Theory#Combinatory_Logic|combinatory logic]]). Changing the names of bound variables within a λ-expression preserves ''ɑ-equivalence''.
 
====BNF grammar====
<pre>λ-term ::= λ-app | λ-abst | var
λ-app ::= λ-term λ-term
λ-abst ::= 'λ'var'.' λ-term</pre>
====Encodings====
The integers (or any countably infinite set) can be represented via the [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Church_encoding Church encoding] (or [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Mogensen-Scott_encoding Mogensen-Scott], or others):
The integers (or any countably infinite set) can be represented via the [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Church_encoding Church encoding] (or [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Mogensen-Scott_encoding Mogensen-Scott], or others):
* <tt>0 ≡ λf. λx. x</tt>
* <tt>0 ≡ λf. λx. x</tt>

Revision as of 06:54, 7 December 2009

The Church-Turing thesis equates a vaguely-defined set of "computable" functions with the partial recursive functions. Several systems are only as powerful as the partial recursives (Turing-complete): Turing machines and the λ-calculus are two. Programming languages provide further syntaxes and semantics.

Applicative/Functional Programming

Expressions compose functions rather than values. Backus proposed three tiers of complexity in his Turing Award lecture:

  • Simply functional language (fp): No state, limited names, finitely many functional forms, simple substitution semantics, algebraic laws
  • Formal functional system (ffp): Extensible functional forms, functions represented by objects, translation of object representation to applicable form, formal semantics
  • Applicative state transition system (ast): ffp plus mutable state and coarse-grained operations thereupon

Higher-order functions map one or more functions to a function.

Combinatory Logic

All you really need in life.

SKI Calculus

  • I ≡ λx. x
  • K ≡ λx, y. x
  • S ≡ λx, y, z. (x z (y z))

Fixed-Point Combinators

Higher-order functions which compute the fixed points of their inputs. Curry's Y-combinator was the first:

  • Y ≡ λf. (λx. f (x x)) (λx. f (x x)) (untyped λ-calculus)
  • Y ≡ S (K (S I I)) (S (S (K S) K) (K (S I I))) (SKI calculus)

Divergence-free evaluation of the Y-combinator requires call-by-name semantics. Call-by-value semantics can make use of the Θv (Turing) or Z-combinators:

  • Θv ≡ (λx. λy. (y (λz. x x y z))) (λx. λy. (y (λz. x x y z)))
  • Z ≡ λf. (λx. f (λy. x x y)) (λx. f (λy. x x y)) (via η-expansion on Y)

The infinitely many fixed-point combinators of untyped λ-calculus are recursively enumerable.

Untyped λ-calculus

Two operators (function definition and application) upon one operand type (λ-expression).

  • Function definition: boundparam. body)
  • Function application: function(actualparam)

The body is made up of free and bound variables. Those not present in the λ's list of bound variables are free. A λ-expression with no free variables is closed (closed expressions are equivalent in power to combinatory logic). Changing the names of bound variables within a λ-expression preserves ɑ-equivalence.

BNF grammar

λ-term ::= λ-app | λ-abst | var
λ-app ::= λ-term λ-term
λ-abst ::= 'λ'var'.' λ-term

Encodings

The integers (or any countably infinite set) can be represented via the Church encoding (or Mogensen-Scott, or others):

  • 0 ≡ λf. λx. x
  • 1 ≡ λf. λx. f x
  • 2 ≡ λf. λx. f (f x)
  • 3 ≡ λf. λx. f (f (f x))
  • n ≡ λf. λx. fnx

The Church booleans take two arguments, and evaluate to one of them:

  • true ≡ λa. λb . a
  • false ≡ λa. λb . b

Some basic operations:

  • plus ≡ λm. λn. λf. λx. m f (n f x) (from f(m + n)(x) = fm(fn(x)))
  • succ ≡ λn. λf. λx. f (n f x) (β-equivalent to (plus 1) for a defined 1)
  • mult ≡ λm. λn. λf. n (m f) (from f(m * n) = (fm)n)

Common syntactic sugar:

  • Left-associative application as implicit parentheses
  • Use of definitions (allowing identifiers to stand in as λ-expressions)
  • Currying: (λx, y. x + y) rather than (λx. (λy. x + y))
  • Numeric literals rather than Church encoding